First published August 10, 2001, in National Review
Online.
HATS OFF to Stanley Kurtz for one of the most thoughtful
conservative treatments yet of gay marriage ("Love and Marriage" and The Right Balance). Kurtz has advanced the
argument on both the social-policy and the constitutional side of
the issue. Let me see if I can advance it further still, starting
with his argument that sex difference lies at the core of
successful marriage.
I've argued that marriage will have many of the same
domesticating and healthful effects on homosexuals as on
heterosexuals. Kurtz argues, by contrast, that it is women, not
marriage, that domesticate men. Traditional marriage, in this view,
is a male-female bargain: The man exchanges promiscuity for
security and a stable love life. Male-male spouses, however, will
continue to be promiscuous within marriage. This will weaken
marriage itself. "A world of same-sex marriages is a world of
no-strings heterosexual hookups and 50 percent divorce rates."
Indeed, "our increased tolerance for homosexuality" is already part
and parcel of "the weakening of marriage."
There are some important cavils with this line of thinking, the
most obvious being (1) that it offers no argument against same-sex
marriage for lesbians, (2) that America is already "a world of
no-strings heterosexual hookups and 50 percent divorce rates" and
has been for years, and (3) that "tolerance for homosexuality" is
at most a trivial cause of marriage's problems compared with such
factors as liberalized divorce laws, women's increased economic
independence, the spread of contraception, the decline of the
shotgun wedding, and the cultural changes of the 1960s and 1970s.
Still, Kurtz's argument goes deeper and deserves a deeper
reply.
I think he's right that women (and children) domesticate lusty
men. That's why everyone is so happy when the town bully takes a
bride. But - a crucial point - women and children are not the
only things that domesticate men. Marriage itself also
does so. The reason is that marriage is not a piece of paper
ratifying a pre-existing relationship. It is a caregiving contract
that two people make not just with each other but with society, and
it's enforced with a whole bundle of rituals and expectations, from
public gestures like weddings and rings and anniversary banquets to
in-laws and shared finances and joint party invitations addressed
to both spouses. Far from being a rubber stamp, marriage is a
culture that actively binds people together.
Will extending this culture to homosexuals damage it by
ratifying rampant promiscuity, or strengthen it by affirming and
extending its reach? This is a question that can only be answered
empirically, which is why gay marriage should be tried in a few
states (see below). But we do have quite a bit of suggestive
evidence, in the form of existing homosexual unions of the
all-but-married sort. Of the ones I know, I can't think of any that
don't aspire to aspire to fidelity and lifetime commitment, even
without a woman in the house. More important, when they fail in
this aspiration, they do so in private, so as not to embarrass each
other or their friends and family, who accept and respect their
partnership. That's all we ask of straights.
In the real world, some married heterosexuals play around a lot
(even if they're president), some play around not at all, and some
play around a little and get over it. All, however, are allowed to
marry. It might be true that on average male-male pairs
will be less faithful than male-female ones, who in turn will
probably be less faithful on average than female-female
ones. But if the question is whether gay marriage should be legal,
rather than exactly what any given marriage looks like, those are
the wrong averages to look at. Here are the right ones: The average
married homosexual man will almost certainly be much less wanton
than the average unmarried homosexual man. And I think it's pretty
likely that even the average unmarried homosexual man will
be significantly less wanton in a gay culture where marriage is
expected than in a one where marriage is illegal.
Really, truly, if I thought that homosexuals would treat
marriage like an orgy and inspire millions of heterosexuals to do
the same, I'd say we're not ready for the privilege. But I don't
think that's remotely likely; Vermont isn't full of orgies posing
as civil unions. And it's at least as plausible that gay marriage
will strengthen marriage as weaken it. When homosexual couples can
legally commit to each other for a lifetime, they, too, will be
able to say to each other: "If you really care about me, as opposed
to just wanting to have sex with me, you'll marry me." Many,
probably most, homosexual men want to get off the market and settle
down, but it's hard to sort out the serious partners if marriage
isn't an option. Allow gays to marry, you don't wreck proper
courtship - you allow it to begin. I'm not saying that male-male or
female-female courtship is identical to male-female courtship (not
that any two are alike anyway). But it doesn't need to be. It only
needs to work better than, "If you really care about me, you'll
move in with me."
When I started to understand I was gay, a particularly bitter
realization was that, whatever the future might hold for me, it
would not hold marriage. A life without the possibility of marriage
is a deprivation so severe that most heterosexuals can't even
imagine it. If I'm right, same-sex marriage will give stability and
care and comfort to millions of homosexuals at little or no cost to
anyone else. If I'm wrong, it's not a good idea. The only way to
find out is to try and see, which is why I favor a federalist
approach that lets some state experiment with same-sex marriage
when it feels the time and circumstances are right.
In his second article, Kurtz argues that my federalist approach
is a daydream. For one thing, the courts might not go along with
it. Kurtz is certainly right that the constitutionality of the
Defense of Marriage Act, which says that no state need recognize
any other's same-sex marriage, will be challenged in the courts.
Everything is challenged in the courts. I'm confident that the
courts will uphold the act; I just can't see this or any
foreseeable Supreme Court imposing gay marriage nationally by fiat.
But, of course, there's no telling what courts may do. The answer
is obvious: Write DOMA into the Constitution. An amendment saying,
"Nothing in this Constitution shall require any state to recognize
as a marriage any union but that of one man and one woman," does
the trick. End of problem.
Such an amendment would be much less controversial, and much
easier to pass, than the one that the would-be amenders have
actually proposed, which bans gay marriage altogether. Why the "not
one inch" position, which says that same-sex marriage must never be
allowed on even one square inch of U.S. soil, regardless of what
the people of any state want? Because, says Kurtz, even if states
are not required by the courts to recognize other states' gay
marriages, they will be driven to do so by practicalities.
Now, hold on there. It's true that having only a few states
recognize gay marriage would lead to confusions and legal tangles.
This, however, is what's known as federalism. In other contexts -
tax law, corporate charters, environmental rules - we live with
confusingly disparate state laws routinely, as any attorney for a
national bank will be quick to confirm. It's a hassle, but the
benefit is enormous: the ability to experiment with different
policies and to let local people create a social and legal climate
that suits them (or move to a state where they'll be happier).
My guess is that, after an initial period of confusion, states
and the courts would fairly quickly develop workable rules for gay
marriage. For instance, a state that had a partnership program
might automatically include any resident gay couple with an
out-of-state marriage licenses. States that firmly object to
same-sex unions, by contrast, will simply tell those couples,
"Sorry, you're not officially married here. If you want to be
officially married, stay there. Here, you need to write a will."
This doesn't seem "next to impossible." It doesn't even seem very
difficult. Compared to the headaches of interstate banking laws,
it's a piece of cake.
And what's the alternative? National culture war. Support for
gay marriage, now at 35 percent, is likely to grow over time, and
the argument is passionate. Kurtz's insistence on "all or nothing"
risks turning same-sex marriage into the next abortion issue, in
which the stakes are so high - national imposition of gay marriage
versus national abolition - that extremism runs riot on both sides.
And what if Kurtz et al. gamble on all-or-nothing and lose? What if
they refuse to try federalism and they fail to pass their
constitutional ban and the courts actually do rule that all states
must recognize one state's same-sex marriages? Then their rejection
of federalism will have brought about exactly the nightmare they
feared. If that happens, don't blame us homosexuals for polarizing
the argument and "ramming homosexual marriage down the country's
throat."
Believe me, Mr. Kurtz: Federalism is the solution, not the
problem. At the very least, it should be given a chance. Isn't that
what conservatives always tell liberals?
Thanks to Stanley Kurtz for another provocative and richly argued article.
Shall we drill a little deeper? If I read him correctly, his
argument boils down to something like this:
- Marriage is rooted essentially in "the underlying dynamic of
male-female sexuality." Nothing else can sustain marriage.
- As a result, it is simply impossible for same-sex (especially
male-male) couples to be good marital citizens. They may get
married, but they won't act married, and society won't treat them
as married.
- Because homosexuals will do a bad job of "exemplifying modern
marriage for the nation" and marriage is in bad enough shape
already, homosexuals should not be allowed to marry.
- Allowing same-sex marriage anywhere in America at any time is
effectively the same as mandating it everywhere forever. So
same-sex marriage must never be tried anywhere, ever.
Or, to put it a bit coarsely: "I don't believe homosexuals can
handle marriage responsibly. And they should never be allowed a
chance to prove me wrong. Sorry, gay people, but that's life."
Kurtzism, as I'll take the liberty of calling this approach,
gets four things wrong. It misanalyzes marriage. It misunderstands
homosexuality. It sits crosswise with liberalism. And it traduces
federalism. Other than that, no problem.
Start with Proposition 1. Kurtz argues that, whatever else
marriage is about, ultimately and indispensably it's about "the
underlying dynamic of male-female sexuality." I'm not sure exactly
what this means beyond saying that marriage must be between a man
and a woman, so I'm not sure how to address it specifically. Here
is what I think marriage is indispensably about: the commitment to
care for another person, for better or worse, in sickness and in
health, till death do you part.
A marriage can and often does flourish long after the passion
has faded, long after the children have gone, and (yes) long after
infidelity; it can flourish without children and even without sex.
A marriage is a real marriage as long as the spouses continue to
affirm that caring for and supporting and comforting each other is
the most important task in their lives. A golden anniversary is not
a great event because both spouses have held up their end of a
"dynamic of male-female sexuality" but because 50 years of devotion
is just about the noblest thing that human beings can achieve.
I can't prove I'm right and Kurtz is wrong. But I think my view
is much closer to what people actually think their marriages are
fundamentally about, and also, by the way, to what marriage should
be fundamentally about. Most married people I know regard
themselves as more or less equal partners in an intricate
relationship whose essential ingredient is the lifelong caregiving
contract. Obviously, they'd agree that male-female sexual dynamics
play an important role in their marriage; but then, they're
male-female couples, so they would say that. If you told
them that marriage is fundamentally about (in Kurtz's words) "a
man's responsibilities to a woman," rather than a person's
responsibilities to a person, they'd look at you funny.
Why is Kurtz so reluctant to put commitment instead of sex roles
at the center of marriage? Because, I suspect, he knows homosexuals
can form commitments. To cut off this pass, he claims that in
practice homosexuals too often won't form commitments (Proposition
2). Same-sex couples, or in any case male same-sex couples, won't
act married, and society won't be bothered if they don't, so
marriage will become a hollow shell.
I've explained why I believe that a world where everyone,
straight and gay, can grow up aspiring to marry will be a world
where gays and straights and marriage are all better off. Kurtz has
explained why he thinks otherwise. All of that is well and good,
but it only gets us so far, because the key questions are all
empirical. How would married gay couples behave? How would married
heterosexuals react? Unfortunately, we have no direct evidence. One
can say that in Vermont, which has a civil-union law, "the
institution of marriage has not collapsed," as the governor
recently said. One can say that gay men (no one seems worried about
lesbians not taking marriage seriously) represent probably 3
percent of the population, and that it seems a stretch to insist
that the 97 percent will emulate the 3 percent. But none of that
proves anything. Absent some actual experience with same-sex
marriage, everything is conjecture.
Still, I think Kurtz's conjecture is based on a view of
homosexuality that is both misguided and at least unintentionally
demeaning. His article contains this arresting phrase: "As the
ultimate symbol of the detachment of sexuality from reproduction,
homosexuality embodies the sixties ethos of sexual
self-fulfillment." So there you are. My relationship with my
partner Michael is about "sexual self-fulfillment," because, I
guess, we can't have children. Let me gently but passionately say
to Kurtz that this is an affront. It implies that a straight man's
life partner is his wife, while a gay man's life partner is just
his squeeze. Let me also gently but firmly instruct Kurtz on a
point that I and other homosexuals are in a position to know
something about. Our partners are not walking dildos and vibrators.
Our partners are our companions, our soulmates, our
loves.
I'm not familiar with the Stiers book he cites and I couldn't
get it on deadline, so I can't comment on it. I can say, though,
that I wouldn't be the least surprised if right now, in 2001, grown
gay men and women often regard marriage as a novelty or a
convenient benefits package. What does Kurtz expect? These are
people who grew up knowing they could never marry, who have
structured their whole lives outside of marriage, and who have of
necessity built their relationships as alternatives to
marriage.
I don't expect that homosexuals will all flock to the altar the
day after marriage is legalized. You don't take a culture that has
been defined forever by exclusion from marriage and expect it to
change overnight. I do think that, a few years after legalization,
we'll see something new: A whole generation of homosexuals growing
up knowing that they can marry, seeing successfully married gay
couples out and about, and often being encouraged to marry by their
parents and mentors. Making the closet culture the exception rather
than the rule for young gay people was the work of one or maybe two
generations. The shift to a normative marriage culture may happen
just as fast.
I know, I know. Kurtz will simply insist that real, committed
marriage will never be normative for homosexuals; gays just don't
have that "dynamic of male-female sexuality" thing. Unfortunately,
I don't think I can persuade him by telling him about all the gay
people I know who have committed their enduring love and care to
each other. I doubt I could persuade him even by telling him about
all the men I know who have fed and comforted and carried their
dying partners, and covered their partners with their bodies to
keep them warm, and held their hands at the end and then sobbed and
sobbed. Who is more fit to marry, the homosexual who comes home
every night to wipe the vomit from the chin of his wasting partner,
or the heterosexual who serves his first wife with divorce papers
while she is in the hospital with cancer so that he can get on with
marrying his second wife? Alas, I think I know what Kurtz would
say.
Kurtz cites figures on gay men's fidelity and attitudes toward
monogamy. There are lots of problems with these kinds of numbers,
but the more interesting question is: Just what does Kurtz think
this kind of data proves? Exactly how monogamous do homosexuals
have to be in order to earn the right to marry? I'd have thought
that being better than 80 percent faithful would be pretty darn
good. Would 90 percent satisfy him? Maybe 98.2 percent? And if a
group's average fidelity is the qualification for marriage,
shouldn't Kurtz let lesbians marry right now? And why are
homosexuals the only class of people who are not allowed to marry
until they prove, in advance, that they'll be good marital
citizens? Last time I checked, heterosexual men were allowed to
take a fifth wife, no questions asked, even if they beat their
first, abandoned their second, cheated on their third, and attended
orgies with their fourth.
For centuries, homosexuals have been barred from marrying and
even from having open relationships. The message has been: Furtive,
underground sex is all homosexuals deserve. And now Kurtz is
insisting (Proposition 3) that homosexuals can't wed because we're
not as sexually well-behaved as married heterosexuals? While also
insisting that, no matter how badly heterosexuals behave, their
right to marry will go unquestioned? Really, the gall!
Forgive my ill temper on that point. I understand that, to Kurtz
and many other Americans, same-sex marriage seems a radical
concept, an abuse of the term "marriage." What I think Kurtz and
too many other opponents of gay marriage fail to appreciate is the
radicalism of telling millions of Americans that they can never
marry anybody they love. To be prohibited from taking a spouse is
not a minor inconvenience. It is a lacerating deprivation.
Marriage, probably more even than voting and owning property and
having children, is the core element of aspiration to the
good life. Kurtz would deprive all homosexuals of any shot at it
lest some of them set a poor example. I think this is both inhumane
and cuts against liberalism's core principle, which is that people
are to be treated ends in themselves, not as means to some
utilitarian social end. I am grateful to Kurtz for leaving the door
open to domestic-partnership programs as a consolation prize; this
is a good-hearted gesture, and I accept it as such. But surely he
recognizes that domestic partnership is no substitute for
matrimony. Surely, indeed, that is his point in offering it.
Same-sex marriage is too important to be approached
thoughtlessly. I'm glad that Kurtz is thinking as strenuously about
the possible downsides as I am about the possible upsides. Where he
veers toward something like extremism is in his demand that
homosexuals be denied any chance to prove his conjectures wrong
(Proposition 4). "There is no such thing as an experiment in gay
marriage," he says. "Rauch seems to think that if his cost-free
portrait of gay marriage turns out to be mistaken, we can simply
call off the experiment. But by then it will surely be too late.
Such effects take years to play out, decades more to measure, and
even when measured, agreement on the meaning of such data is nearly
impossible to achieve."
But pretty nearly all major social-policy reforms play out over
years and decades, and agreement on how to measure the results is
never complete; Kurtz might just as well say that no state should
be allowed to try welfare reform or charter schools or a "living
wage" because the effects take years to play out, decades to
measure, etc. The whole point of federalism is to allow states to
try reforms that might not work, and to allow states'
voters not me or Stanley Kurtz to decide for themselves what counts
as working. In rejecting this principle root and branch, Kurtz
emerges as a radical enemy not just of same-sex marriage but of
federalism itself.
I don't have much new to say about his peculiar claim that, once
any state adopts same-sex marriage, every other state will have to
follow, because Kurtz doesn't have anything new to say defending
it. He simply re-asserts it. "Imagine a married couple, where one
spouse is hospitalized after a car accident in another state,
losing visiting rights or the right to make medical decisions,
because their marriage isn't recognized in that state," he says, as
if the situation is obviously untenable. OK, I've imagined it. That
kind of arrangement would be perfectly manageable. Gay spouses in a
state with same-sex marriage would understand that they will need a
medical power of attorney that's valid out-of-state. None of these
complexities is remotely thorny enough to force any state to
recognize same-sex marriage against its will. It seems to me that
what Kurtz really fears is that one state will adopt same-sex
marriage and others will look at it and say, "Actually, that
doesn't seem so bad pretty good, even. We don't mind recognizing it
even if we don't adopt it ourselves." What he really fears, in
other words, is not a disastrous state experiment but a successful
one.
Again Kurtz asserts that federal judges will high-handedly
impose one state's same-sex marriages on all the others. Again I
say that there is just as he says plenty of room in the law for
determined judges to decide this legal issue either way, but that
any sane Supreme Court will be determined not to impose same-sex
marriage on an unwilling nation. And if undemocratic judicial fiat
is what worries Kurtz, why does he greet with silence my suggestion
that a simple constitutional amendment far easier to pass than the
one he supports would solve the problem?
But all of this stuff about states' being "forced" to accept
same-sex marriage is a red herring. Kurtz makes it clear that he is
no happier if a state adopts same-sex marriage by legislation or
plebiscite than by judicial fiat. His proposed constitutional
amendment accordingly strips states, and not just judges, of the
power to permit same-sex marriage, even if everybody in some state
wants to try it. What I suspect Kurtz really knows and fears is
that as more homosexuals form devoted and visible unions, and as
more of the public accepts and honors those unions, same-sex
marriage will seem ever less strange and radical, and ever more in
harmony with Americans' core values which it is. Although he fears
that same-sex marriage will come to pass over the public's
objections, he fears even more that it will come to pass with the
public's assent.
I read Stanley Kurtz's latest contribution to our gay-marriage
discussion several times, and I came away concluding that his
position really does, as I said last time, essentially boil down
to: "I don't believe homosexuals can handle marriage responsibly.
And they should never be allowed a chance to prove me wrong. Sorry,
gay people, but that's life."
Although I do think it's wrong to demand that homosexuals who
want to marry prove they'll meet sexual-behavior standards that are
never applied to heterosexuals, I don't believe that homosexuals
have an absolute right to marriage, and I've been careful,
pace Kurtz, not to rest my case on rights. (When I talk
casually about, for example, "denying homosexuals the right to
marry," I mean 'right' only in the weaker sense of statutory
entitlement.) If I thought that legalizing same-sex marriage would
destroy or seriously damage marriage for everyone, then I would
oppose same-sex marriage as a self-defeating entitlement. My
argument is one about presumption. If there is significant
doubt about the effects of same-sex marriage and of course neither
Kurtz nor I nor anybody else really knows what would happen, and in
truth many good and bad and indifferent things would happen then
the presumption ought to be that everyone should have a chance to
participate in society's most important civic institution. At a
bare minimum, if the claim is that homosexuals will wreck marriage,
we should not be forever denied any hope of showing that we won't
wreck marriage.
It means a lot to me to hear Kurtz say that there is an
"inescapable element of tragedy" in having to deny marriage to
homosexuals in order to preserve it for everybody else. Many
conservatives, probably almost all until very recently, have viewed
gay lives and loves as a more or less inconsequential factor in the
debate over gay marriage. Their attitude has been, "Why do these
homosexuals insist on wrecking marriage? Why don't they just go
away and leave well enough alone? So what if they can't marry? Pass
the potato chips." Kurtz will have none of that. I thank him.
But "so sorry" only gets Kurtz so far if the tragedy is of his
own making. If he really believes that denying marriage to
homosexuals is tragic, he should seek to avoid rather than
perpetuate the tragedy. If there is any reasonable possibility that
the alleged tragic trade-off between gay and straight marriage is
imaginary that same-sex and opposite-sex marriage could happily
coexist he should look for and embrace a reasonable option that
could test that possibility. One such option is to let our
federalist system run its course, letting individual states try
same-sex marriage if and when they please. Then we'll see what
happens. Yet it is Kurtz who seeks to foreclose this option, with a
constitutional amendment banning same-sex marriage. He would thus
rule tragedy into being: tragedy in the form of perpetual
homosexual alienation from the social institution that's most
important for a happy and healthy life. For all that I appreciate
Kurtz's stated solicitousness of gay lives and loves and believe
me, I do it may be that the old-fashioned conservative "We don't
care" was in some ways more honest.
How would we know if gay marriage works? Kurtz charges that it
would be very hard ever to persuade me that a state gay-marriage
experiment failed, and that I "will clearly oppose a rollback, on
principle, anytime before the next 50 years." Here, I think, Kurtz
again misapprehends federalist (and democratic) principle. The
question isn't what Jonathan Rauch or Stanley Kurtz or any other
pointy-head thinks of a state's experience with gay marriage; the
question is what the people of that state and of other states
think. The whole point of a federalist approach is that it lets the
voters of the states decide what sort of arrangement counts as a
social-policy success. I will accept their judgment. Why won't
he?
Well, on that subject I think Kurtz and I have reached the point
of repeating ourselves. Anyway, I've reached that point. So I'll
leave the arguments before the reader and pass on to a couple of
other threads. Kurtz says that I'm at the conservative end of the
gay intelligentsia on marriage, and that a lot of gay radicals and
intellectuals think I'm wrong. That's certainly true, but I don't
see why it's important. Gay radicals and intellectuals think all
sorts of things but are no more likely than anyone else to be
right; it's the argument and evidence, not the source, that counts.
I think the gay left-winger who says gay matrimony will undermine
the norms of marriage is just as wrong as the conservative
right-winger who says it. What else can I say?
In any case, the gay intelligentsia are all over the map on
marriage. Not long ago, in an article in Reason magazine,
I dissected a book by Michael Warner, a prominent and very smart
gay radical who argues that sexual norms of any kind are
oppressive. He loathes the idea of same-sex marriage precisely
because "the effect would be to reinforce the material privileges
and cultural normativity of marriage," which would reduce the
amount of sexual experimentation going on, which he thinks would be
awful. As I'm sure Kurtz knows, there are a lot of gay radicals who
share Warner's fear that marriage will change gay culture in
appallingly bourgeois ways. Does that show I'm right? Really, I
don't think brandishing gay intellectuals gets us anywhere.
It may be more productive to focus on an odd convergence of
interests between the world's Michael Warners and Stanley Kurtzes.
Warner and his ilk dislike gay marriage, but they can't be against
it because they think homosexuals should have equal rights,
including the right to marry. So how do they get out of this box?
By arguing for a multiplicity of alternatives to marriage, thus
eroding marriage's unique prestige.
Don't get me wrong; if I can't get gay marriage, I'll
reluctantly take partnership programs, which would do at least
something to recognize and nourish stable gay relationships. But
from a social point of view, a partnership program indeed, anything
that competes with marriage is a poor second choice. Most
gay-marriage opponents just say, "Fine, then homosexuals should get
nothing." But a few more compassionate and far-sighted opponents
people like Kurtz understand that telling homosexuals to go fly a
kite is not an option. Americans really believe in the Golden Rule,
equal opportunity to pursue happiness, and all that. They're going
to want to do something for homosexuals, a desire that
will increase as more sons and daughters and siblings and friends
come out.
Something really new, without historical precedent, is happening
in America. Today, for the first time, a majority is coming to
realize that homosexuals actually exist: that we're not just
heterosexuals who need treatment or jail. This realization will,
must, and should drive change in a society whose institutions are
premised on the notion that homosexuals do not actually exist. The
question is whether marriage or something else should be the
template. If there's one social regularity I can think of, it's
that marriage the commitment to care for another person for life
has good effects on human populations, and that its denial has bad
effects, and that the alternatives are worse. But if Kurtz
absolutely cannot accept that this might be true in the case of
same-sex unions, then he had better start planning for a nation
full of Vermonts, with all kinds of sort-of-marriage programs.
Note that, once partnership programs are set up, heterosexuals
who don't want to get married invariably clamor to get in. "How
come only the gays get this? No special rights!" As of 1998, all
three of the states and all but a handful of the municipalities
that offered domestic-partner programs for their workers included
opposite-sex couples; so did the large majority of corporate
programs. I grant that to some extent "marriage lite" will spread
anyway, because some states that bar gay marriage will offer
alternatives. But a constitutional ban on gay marriage will force
all states that want to do anything for homosexuals to create
alternatives to marriage. Employers, too, will create multifarious
partnership programs that would be unnecessary if homosexuals could
just get married. Is all this good for marriage? Kurtz worries
about "the dissolution of marriage and its replacement by an
infinitely flexible series of relationship contracts." But that is
exactly what he guarantees by withholding the template of
marriage!
Polygamy, which rears its ugly head in Kurtz's last paragraph
and in his argument against Andrew Sullivan, merits a
discussion of its own; here, just a few words. On grounds of both
equality and social policy, gay marriage is completely consonant
with liberal principles, and polygamy just as completely isn't and
the distinction is not hard to understand and sustain. Homosexuals
are not asking for the legal right to marry anybody or everybody we
love. We are asking for precisely and only the same legal right
that heterosexuals enjoy, namely the right to marry
somebody we love: one person, as opposed to no one at all.
Liberalism holds that similarly situated people should be similarly
treated by law. Americans increasingly understand that a gay man
who is allowed to marry a woman is not situated similarly to a
straight man who is allowed to marry a woman. Nor is a gay man who
wants to marry a man situated similarly to a straight man who wants
to marry three women or a man who wants to marry his dog or his
Volkswagen; he is situated similarly to a heterosexual man who
wants to marry one woman. Saying that gay marriage leads to
polygamy is no more logically coherent than saying that if blacks
(say) demand and are given one vote, whites (say) will inevitably
demand and be given two.
Moreover, a liberal regime has a strong social-policy interest
in making marriage universal. There's a reason why no polygamous
countries are liberal: if some men usually high-status men get
multiple wives, then by definition other men usually low-status men
get no wives. The result is a restless and destabilizing sexual
underclass that must be subdued by some form of repression. Not
coincidentally, gay culture, in its own way, for many years had
some characteristics of a restless and destabilizing sexual
underclass, and it was subdued to some extent by repression. That
all began to change when open gay relationships started becoming
socially acceptable. Gay marriage is, obviously, completely
consonant with liberal aspirations to make marriage something that
everyone can aspire to. In fact, it fulfills those aspirations.